Getting it wrong from the beginning: The mismatch between
school and children's minds Our Progressivist Inheritance from Herbert Spencer,
John Dewey, and Jean Piaget
Kieran Egan
K.
Egan explains how we have come to take mistaken concepts (Spencer en Co) about
education for granted and why this dooms our attempts at educational reform
Introduction
What have we been getting wrong from the beginning? And when
was the beginning the title refers to? I will argue that we have been getting
education wrong from the beginning, and the beginning I am concerned with is
that of public schooling in the late nineteenth century. All societies, as far
as our anthropology can tell, have had some formal initiation process for the
young, and schools have existed in the West for millennia. But the school as we
know it was an invention of the late nineteenth century. Before that time
education was very largely a process of preparing males for leadership roles in
society, whereas the apparatus for schooling everybody for participation in a
democracy is quite recent.
In this paper I will argue that the conception of education
that continues to shape our schools, and influences what we do to children in
its name, was given its modern sense as a result of ideas that were largely
formulated in the 1850s. I will try to show the source of many of our present
most generally held beliefs about learning, development, and the curriculum,
and show that they were based on ideas that were, simply, wrong. These ideas
continue to be the source of catastrophic damage and waste of life, and are
responsible for the general ineffectiveness of schooling.
In describing a catastrophe one needs an appropriate
villain, and the best villain of modern education is Herbert Spencer
(1829-1903). In my experience the ideas of most teachers and professors of
education I encounter are&emdash;usually quite unbeknownst to
them&emdash;Herbert Spencer's. He was an odd character, perhaps most
vividly captured in Beatrice Webb's My Apprenticeship (1926/1971). He stood at
the crux of the modern world, when the heroic intellectual activity of
Victorians was secularizing the Western world and setting in place the
scientific and scholarly agendas we are still very largely following. Spencer
was a prolific writer, of immense influence during the nineteenth-century. He
visited America and gave triumphant lectures, influencing profoundly, among
others, educators like Dewey, Thorndyke, Parker, Hall, and many others. As the
historian of education Lawrence Cremin put it, describing the revolution that
became progressivism: "If the revolution had a beginning, it was surely
with the work of Herbert Spencer" (Cremin, 1961, p. 91).
The trouble with Spencer . . . well, there are many
troubles, but the particularly relevant trouble here is that pretty-well all
his ideas were wrong. By the end of the 19th century, he was a deeply
disappointed man. His great synthesizing works were dismissed as irrelevant,
his evolutionary theory&emdash;that preceded Darwin's in
publication&emdash;remained Lamarckian, the bases of his biological
theorizing were shown to be false, his social ideas were accepted only by the
most virulently right-wing exploiters (not so small a group, of course). But
his educational ideas, based on general principles shown to be false, became
the rarely-questioned basis of modern education.
If Spencer has been so influential, why is he so little
know?
Before dealing with Spencer's ideas on education, I should
address what may seem to be a puzzle. If Spencer is so central to the
construction of the schools of today, and has consequently had a profound
influence especially upon everyone educated in America, how is it that his name
is almost forgotten, even within educational discourse?
Herbert Spencer's name is perhaps known in a vague way by
many professors of education, but most teachers have never heard of him. If he
is mentioned in textbooks, it is usually in a casual footnote, or in a
reference to his extreme answer to his still disturbing, though daft, question,
"What knowledge is of most worth?" Even those I have mentioned as
profoundly influenced by him&emdash;Dewey, James, Parker, Hall,
Thorndike&emdash;are niggardly with acknowledgements to Spencer, and his
name appears in their writings most commonly when they are refuting one or
other of his prodigal ideas. How could someone virtually no-one today reads be
the source of ideas nearly everyone in Education accepts without question? How
can an obscure Victorian provide a key to understanding the ineffectiveness of
much modern schooling? If his ideas were so wrong, surely the experiments of a
pragmatic educational system over the past century or more will have exposed
the error?
Spencer's voluminous writings bring to mind what was one of
the most famous Victorian cartoons to appear in the British humor magazine,
Punch. The cartoon was known as 'the curate's egg'. At two ends of a long table
sit a weedy, nervous young curate and a portly, domineering Archbishop. They
are having boiled eggs for breakfast, and the wavy lines rising from the
curate's egg indicate it is bad. The Archbishop says, "Ah, Arbuthnot, your
egg appears to be bad." The diffident curate replies, "Oh no, my
Lord. Parts of it are excellent."
Spencer's work, as the century wore on, came to be seen as
curate's egg-ish. Parts of it may have been excellent, but the bad parts were
found so unpalatable that his great influence dissipated rapidly. I will
mention six reasons for this decline, focusing particularly on those connected
with educators' reluctance to acknowledge him as their source.
First, those who enthusiastically adopted Spencer's
educational ideas for the new public schools faced the embarrassment that
Spencer himself argued resolutely against any provision of education by the
state, especially for the lower classes. To people like John Dewey, who were
concerned deliberately to expand public schooling, using the state's control of
schooling to reconstruct society through educational reform, Spencer's views
were, to say the least, inconvenient. This was especially so because the
general principles from which he derived the progressive educational ideas they
liked were also the principles on which he founded his opposition to public
schooling. His version of social evolution led him to believe that the weak,
poor, and unintelligent should be discouraged from breeding, and education and
other social welfare programs only served to maintain incompetents and so slow
down the beneficent progress nature has in store for us.
Second, the ideas commonly labeled "social
Darwinism" might be better called "social Spencerism." "The
survival of the fittest" was originally Spencer's term, even though Darwin
did later use it in a limited way. Spencer extended the idea of the survival of
the fittest from natural selection to pretty well everything in sight. When he
applied it to society and economic systems, he argued for what has been called,
by a British Prime Minister, Edward Heath, "the unacceptable face of
capitalism"&emdash;that is, the exploitation of the poor, weak, and
defenseless by the rich and powerful for the latter's private profit. This
aspect of Spencer's supposedly scientific writings helped account for his great
popularity with one segment of American society. William Sumner
(1840&endash;1910), president of Yale University, enthusiastically used
these ideas of Spencer's to argue for the freedom of capital from state
regulation. Association with a ruthless program of exploitation and suppression
of working people, and with a program of unstinting support for a power élite,
hardly endeared Spencer to socialists like John Dewey or to any of those
wanting to use the new schools to further democratic ideals. Thomas Huxley
summed up Spencer's social ideas as "reasoned savagery" (1951, p.
181).
Third, even at the level of curriculum development, where
Spencer's focus on the whole life of the child and on learning things of
practical value was warmly embraced, his own application of the principles
produced an exclusively science-based curriculum, even in primary school. This
reflected Spencer's own peculiar education by his father, but it seemed simply
eccentric to those who were planning to prepare the young for all aspects of
life in an expanding American society.
Fourth, some of Spencer's fame grew from his having devised
theories about evolution even before Darwin published his arguments and
evidence. Indeed, "evolution" was Spencer's term; Darwin at first
wrote of "descent with modifications" or "natural
selection." Neither had the snappy neatness of Spencer's preferred term,
which became the one generally accepted, even by Darwin. The problem was that
Spencer never really understood Darwin's idea of natural selection. He seems to
have seen Darwin's theory as simply one particular mechanism&emdash;a
clever one undoubtedly&emdash;whereby evolution proceeded, and as just one
small addition to his own vastly more comprehensive philosophical theory of
evolution.
Spencer's scientific understanding never advanced beyond a
rather crude Lamarckian view. Jean Baptiste de Lamarck (1744&endash;1829)
had proposed (in his 1809 Philosophie Zoologique) a groundbreaking theory of
evolution; he argued that changes occurred in species as a result of acquired
characteristics being inherited by future generations. So if a species moves to
a new environment in which, say, a tail no longer serves a useful purpose, the
tail will disappear over generations and other features that are more used will
be enlarged or expanded in some way. This inheritance of acquired
characteristics was used, classically, to account for the giraffe's neck having
stretched over generations so they could better reach the high shoots of tall bushes
and small trees.
Lamarck's general idea of species-change has become very
widely accepted, as has Darwin's explanation of how it occurs. By the end of
the nineteenth century, when Darwin's theory had become more widely understood,
those most committed to evolution considered Spencer out-dated, eccentric, and
ignorant. So evolution's most outspoken champion became a decided
embarrassment. William James, in his 1890 Principles of Psychology, took issue
with Spencer about evolution, pointing out that he simply misunderstood it.
Fifth, on the scientific side matters became even worse for
Spencer. In 1853, the ideas of the German physicist, Hermann von Helmholtz
(1821&endash;94), about energy expenditure were translated into English.
His formulation of the second law of thermodynamics had terrible implications
for the principle from which Spencer had spun most of his general theories,
including his main educational ideas. Spencer had absorbed Karl Ernst von
Baer's (1792&endash;1876) notion of "the law underlying the whole
organic creation" (1851, p. 65)&emdash;that we were parts of an
immense process that moved inexorably from the homogeneous to the
heterogeneous. The second law of thermodynamics predicted the opposite; that
energy was being endlessly dissipated in work, light, and heat, so the cosmos
was moving inexorably to an homogeneously dark, silent, dead universe.
Helmholtz's law led to some panic in mid-century, as
physicists tried to calculate how long the sun could continue to expel its heat
and light before burning out; estimates ranged from a bothersome twenty-five
years to ten million years.
What, then, happens to Spencer's beneficent nature and its
guarantee of progress? Later in the century, as Beatrice Webb touchingly
chronicles, Spencer was a deeply depressed and disappointed man. As she puts
it:
In answer to my inquiry [about why Spencer found the new
physics so disquieting] my friend Bertrand Russell suggests the following
explanation: 'I don't know whether he was ever made to realize the implications
of the second law of thermodynamics; if so, he may well be upset. The law says
that everything tends to uniformity and a dead level, diminishing (not
increasing) heterogeneity' [Letter from Bertrand Russell to Beatrice Webb, 4
June, 1923] (Webb, 1926/71, p. 109n).
We know he was made to realize the implications, by the
Irish physicist, John Tyndall, and Spencer's shaken reaction is on record; he
was indeed deeply disturbed, and remained so more or less till his death.
Sixth: another embarrassment for the educational reformers
was Spencer's belief in recapitulation. This was his fourth guiding principle
for educators: "the education of the child must accord both in mode and
arrangement with the education of mankind, considered historically"
(Spencer, 1859/1911, p. 60). Spencer had also believed that this principle had
been shown to operate in biology, drawing again on von Baer. He followed the
mid-nineteenth-century belief that each human fetus in its development went
through&emdash;recapitulated&emdash;all the stages of development of
our species, from simple-celled creature, through gilled fish-like ancestors,
and so on, to the present. Like so much of the primitive science Spencer picked
up, this too was shown to be false.
But there was clearly ambivalence about this idea among
those Americans who influenced the new schools. G. Stanley Hall was an
enthusiastic believer in educational recapitulation. He believed, with Spencer,
that the child's learning should follow the process whereby the different forms
of knowledge had been built up during cultural history. John Dewey was also
clearly attracted to recapitulation early in his career. He notes that there
"is a sort of natural recurrence of the child mind to the typical
activities of primitive people" (in Gould, 1977, p. 154). Even later,
Dewey occasionally used recapitulationist arguments to support his curriculum
proposals, e.g. "It is pertinent to note that in the history of the race
the sciences grew gradually out from useful social occupations" (1916, pp.
220/201). But, at the same time, he explicitly rejected recapitulation with the
claim that it "tends to make the . . .present a more or less futile
imitation of the past" (1916, p. 75). He saw recapitulation as
incompatible with the educational task to "emancipate the young from the
need of dwelling in an outgrown past" (1916, p. 73). In reaching such a
position he echoes the more forthright rejection of recapitulation made by
Edward L. Thorndike:
Heaven knows that Dame Nature herself in ontogeny [the
development of the modern individual] abbreviates and skips and distorts the
order of the appearance of organs and functions, and for the best of reasons.
We ought to make an effort, as she does, to omit the useless and antiquated and
get to the best and most useful as soon as possible. We ought to change what is
to what ought to be, as far as we can (1913 I, p. 105).
The additional embarrassment about Spencer's
recapitulationism was its casual brutal racism. His theories helped those in
whose interests it was to view other races as inferior "savages",
comparing such adult "savages" with modern children: "During
early years every civilized man passes through that phase of character
exhibited by the barbarous race from which he is descended. As the child's
features&emdash;flat nose, forward-opening nostrils, large lips, wide-apart
eyes, absent frontal sinus, etc.&emdash;resemble for a time those of the
savage, so, too, do his instincts. Hence the tendencies to cruelty, to
thieving, to lying, so general among children" (1911, p. 108). Spencer
used such absurd observations to justify "superior" people's right to
govern "inferior" people, and, of course, to decide who was inferior
and who superior. He tended to pick up any piece of information or observation
that seemed to fit his general scheme, and so support for his recapitulation
idea is full of racist nonsense, nonsense biology, and nonsense linguistics.
Given the American schools' need to prepare huge numbers of immigrant children
for the new society, recapitulation was an unattractive idea, and the support
evinced for it made it even more repellent to most educators.
By the first decades of the twentieth century, then, if you
were an educator attracted by Spencer's principles, you would not likely be keen
to declare yourself a follower of Spencer. The accompanying baggage would be
too burdensome. While American educators might have been ready to still
acknowledge Spencer in the 1880s, it became increasingly convenient to cite
homegrown American authorities who expressed his ideas without reference to
him.
Biologized minds and learning
Let us take the conception of learning that Spencer inferred
from his philosophical researches, which he would prefer to call scientific. In
a brief paper I cannot hope to be more than suggestive about this and the
following claims, so I will just try to locate the points at which Spencer's
seductive errors have led modern educators massively astray.
Like everyone else remotely involved with children and their
education, Spencer observed that children in "the household, the streets
and the fields" (1911, p. 24) learn all kinds of things effortlessly, with
eager pleasure, yet these same children often have great difficulty learning
quite elementary things in formal educational settings. How to explain this
puzzle? Why should children who learn to talk fluently, later find it so
difficult to read and write fluently, or to learn a second language as easily
as the first? Why should children who rapidly become so easily initiated into
the norms and values of one culture find it so difficult to accommodate to
those of another culture later? Why should children who find it easy to learn
the sometimes complex rules of games find it difficult to grasp simple
mathematics?
Spencer believed that his studies in evolutionary theory and
biology had given him the answer: "Grant that the evolution of
intelligence in a child . . . conforms to laws; and it follows inevitably that
education cannot be rightly guided without knowledge of these laws" (1911,
p. 23). So when children fail to learn in schools, the fault lies in methods of
instruction or in the knowledge selected for the curriculum that did not
conform with the laws whereby children's intelligence worked.
The answer was to devise methods of instruction, learning
environments, and a curriculum that did conform with the underlying laws of
children's learning and development. Once methods and curricula more hospitable
to children's learning were in place, their natural desire for knowledge would
be released, and an educational revolution would take place.
The progressivist movement in particular, but many others
too, bought this fools' gold, caught Spencer's disease, and the twentieth
century saw immense amounts of time, energy, ingenuity, and money expended on
trying to make learning in schools match children's spontaneous learning in
household, street, and field&emdash;what today we might call learning
"street smarts". The Holy Grail of progressivism&emdash;to let
the metaphors run free&emdash;has been to discover methods of school
instruction derived from and modeled on children's effortless learning, and so
bring about the revolution promised by Spencer and by progressivists throughout
the twentieth-century. Despite all the ingenuity and effort, the revolution
hasn't shown the faintest signs of occurring.
So what is the error? If one was to try to model human
conceptual development, it would be tempting to say that evolution equipped us
with two kinds of learning. There is, first, that largely effortless learning
of our early years, which we use to pick up a language and conceptions of our
society and the cosmos, and appropriate behavior within them. It seems to work
a bit like cement or plaster-of-Paris; at first it is enormously flexible, able
to adapt to widely varied external constraints, and then gradually it sets and
becomes rigid. It also seems to be focused on very specific
objects&emdash;like language, or social behavior, etc. The second kind of
learning remains flexible throughout our lives and is a kind of all-purpose
utility, but it is much more laborious and slow. The difference between the two
is often said to be evident in the efficiency with which we learn a language
and adapt to social customs in our early years, in contrast with the relative
difficulty and inefficiency with which we learn a new language and adapt to new
social customs later in life.
Jerry Fodor (1983), for one example, suggests we might see
the mind as having particular input systems and a somewhat distinct central
processor. The input systems are relatively specific to particular parts of the
normal brain, they are focused on such things as touch, hearing, seeing, and
language, and they are fast and "stupid"&emdash;we can't not hear
or not learn a language in normal conditions. The central processor is
"smart" and is slow and general in both brain location and
operations. This allows very fast responses to some things by the
"stupid" brain systems and slow contemplation and analysis by the
other. Fodor notes that "it is, no doubt, important to attend to the
eternally beautiful and true. But it is more important not to be eaten"
(1985, p. 4)
Well, we might wisely be cautious in inferring such a sharp
distinction in kinds of learning as we are still unsure about the underlying
cognitive reality such distinctions refer to.
I use Fodor's terms here as a short-hand way of indicating
the error I think has been repeatedly made, even though there may be good
reasons to question much of Fodor's model, as Karmiloff-Smith (1992) for one
among many, has argued. But his model is useful just to indicate why one might
begin to worry about the "common-sense" objective of making
children's learning in schools better conform with their learning in
households, streets, and fields. What Spencer is requiring, in Fodor's terms,
is to make the central processor work like an input system. It won't and can't.
The century and more of attempts to make school-learning more like children's
early effortless learning, has been misdirected.
Spencer's assumptions that there is only a single kind of
learning leads to the belief that all school learning must be equally effortless
as language learning, and it should be invariably pleasurable. If these two
criteria are not satsfied in any learning experience, then there is something
wrong with the method of teaching, or the environment in which it is taking
place, or with the curriculum. He stated his position as follows:
Just as the child incidentally gathers the meanings of
ordinary words from the conversations going on around it, without the help of
dictionaries; so, from the remarks on objects, pictures, and its own drawings,
will it presently acquire, not only without effort but even pleasurably, those
same scientific terms which, when taught at first, are a mystery and a
weariness (Spencer, 1966, p.92).
He uses the rhetoric of progrssivism we have come to find so
familiar, along with its binary distinction between good, active,
child-centered teaching and bad, passive, traditional teaching. With the
progressivist vision before us, the schools will be transformed and children
once "stupified by the ordinary school-drill--by its abstract formulas,
its wearisome tasks, its cramming--have suddenly had their intellects roused by
thus ceasing to make them mere passive recipients, and inducing them to become
active discoverers" (Spencer, 1996, p. 96).
Unilinear development
In 1851 Spencer read a review of W.B. Carpenter's Principles
of Physiology. In his autobiography many years later, Spencer describes this
review as an "incident of moment" in his intellectual life. The
review introduced him to the decades old ideas of K.E. von Baer, and
particularly Baer's claim that all living organisms develop from a condition of
homogeneity to one of increasing heterogeneity. The "incident of
moment" was Spencer's recognition that this formula could be applied to
the evolution of inorganic no less than to organic material, and to individuals
today no less than to species in the past. Indeed&emdash;it could be
applied to everything! It was Spencer's restrained English "Eurika!"
He was not the kind of person to run down the street naked, Archimedes-like,
shouting his discovery but, with proper English reserve, he noted that this
insight allowed him to tie together "thoughts that were previously
unorganized, or but partially organized" (1904, p. 337). He had
discovered, he thought, one of the most fundamental principles of nature.
(Given his contentious relationship with George Elliott, and
the rival claims about who turned down whose proposal of marriage, it does not
require straining to see elements of Spencer in Mr. Casaubon's discovery of
"the key to all mythologies" in Middlemarch.)
When this key to all the process of nature was applied to
education it allowed Spencer to articulate those principles that, as far as I
have been able to tell, are still believed as unassailably true by very many teachers
and professors of education. So it still seems accepted that we should proceed
from the simple to the complex, and from the concrete to the abstract, and from
the empirical to the rational. Also in education: "children should be led
to make their own investigations, and to draw their own inferences. They should
be told as little as possible, and induced to discover as much as
possible" (1911, p. 62). Finally, we must always ask, "Does it create
a pleasurable excitement in the pupils?" (1911, p. 63). He believed that
to "tell a child this and to show it the other, is not to teach it how to
observe, but to make it the mere recipient of another's observations."
The basis for these educational ideas was, first, von Baer's
general homogeneous to heterogeneous principle&emdash;"the law
underlying the whole organic creation" (1851, p. 65). But von Baer was
wrong about organic creation; evolution is rather a process of elaboration in
all directions, lacking the teleological principle favored by von Baer and Spencer
(c.f. Gould, 1977, 1997). As mentioned earlier, Spencer's generalization of the
principle ran afoul of Hermann von Helmholtz second law of thermodynamics,
published in English in 1853. If, as Helmholtz showed, energy was being
constantly dissipated in work, light, and heat, the cosmos was not eternally
due for increasing heterogeneity.
The second basis for Spencer's educational principles was
his evolutionary ideas. These too were wrong. While Spencer drew on Darwin, he
remained always a little irritated that Darwin should have gained such
celebrity, as his evolutionary theory was, in Spencer's view, less general and
powerful than his own. Spencer never really grasped Darwin's theory, or,
rather, never grasped that it undermined the Lamarckian ideas Spencer held to
his death.
The combination of von Baer's idea and Spencer's version of
evolution led him to conclude that the fundamental law of life, the universe,
and everything was "progress". In a celebrated essay written in 1851,
"Progress: Its Law and Cause," Spencer had shown to his and many
other's satisfaction that "progress is not an accident, not a thing within
human control, but a beneficent necessity (1966, p. 60). He had established
that this beneficent necessity was "displayed by the progress of
civilization as a whole, as well as in the progress of every nation; and is
still going on with increasing rapidity" (1966, p. 19).
Spencer had seen the fundamental law giving order to his
observations and studies of evolution, and then of biological processes. His
application of it to the mind followed much the same pattern. He conceived of
the mind as following a process of gradually increasing heterogeneity from
birth to adulthood--in much the same way that is common in developmental
psychology and educationalists today. The mind is assumed to be an organ with a
program that it spontaneously follows, as long as it is provided the
appropriate environment and food. Spencer, that is, articulated explicitly a
conception of the mind based on his biological conceptions. "If it be true
that the mind like the body has a predetermined course of evolution--if it
unfolds spontaneously--if its successive desires for this or that kind of
information arises when these are severally required for its nutrition--if there
thus exists in itself a promter to the right species of activity at the right
time; why interfere in any way?" (Spencer, 1966, p. 67). The job of the
educator, then, is simply to "systematize the natural process" in
order to aid "self-evolution" (Spencer, 1966/1860, pp. 84, 85).
One result of such a view is that the teacher becomes a
facilitator of a process that will unfold ideally if given the right
conditions. The educator is not to shape the mind with knowledge, but to
support with appropriate food/knowledge its spontaneous development. Such a
view also has obvious and radical implications for the curriculum, as we shall
see below.
During the twentieth century, Jean Piaget, most notably, has
continued the quest to expose some putative spontaneous process of intellectual
development. . I am inclined to echo Jerry Fodor's observation about the modern
pursuit of Spencer's dream that exposing the nature of students' psychological
development will be important to education: "Deep down, I'm inclined to
doubt that there is such a thing as cognitive development in the sense that
developmental cognitive psychologists have in mind" (1985, p. 35).
Vygotsky pointed out in response to Piaget that the mind is not just an
epistemological and psychological organ, but is also a social organ. Any
adequate conception of education has to attend to the intellectual tools that
any particular society delivers to its young to mediate their understanding of
the world. Attempts to describe some psychological developmental process that
is somehow independent of those two seems increasingly barren. Whatever results
from these disputes, though, Spencer's fundamental ideas about development were
wrong, and yet the pedagogical practices based on them are still the largely
unquestioned currency of education, with their claims that children can learn
only simple, concrete, local knowledge, and so on.
It is noteworthy that the terms Spencer used-- adaptation,
assimilation, the mind's growth by taking in aliments, etc.--find a place in
the Piagetian scheme. And one might incidentally note that Spencer's profound
influence on the American James Mark Baldwin was passed to the French
psychologist Pierre Janet, with whom Baldwin worked in Paris. The young Jean
Piaget's writings were, in turn, significantly influenced by Janet.
The curriculum
Setting up new schools for all children in a democratic
state focused attention on what one ought to teach them. The old
"ornamental" curriculum designed to enable aristocrats to use their
leisure enjoyably came in for much derision. Spencer broached the topic, and
provided an answer, in his celebrated essay, "What knowledge is of most
worth" (1859).
With his usual brio, he argued that we must sweep away the
old curricula: "Men dress their children's minds as they do their bodies,
in the prevailing fashion" (1911, p. 2). Instead of following fashions, we
need to begin by considering what is most important in life, and prepare
children for that. What is important? Well, he ranks in order self-preservation,
securing the necessaries of life, bringing up children well, producing good
citizens, and, last, prepare them as adults to enjoy nature, literature, and
the fine arts. And what knowledge will best support these aims for education?
Well, the new scientific knowledge relevant to each.
So the prevailing curriculum based in Latin, Greek, and
history was to be swept away. It took some time, but it has pretty well gone.
History was, to Spencer, a "mere tissue of names and dates and dead
unmeaning events . . . it has not the remotest bearings on any of our
actions" (1911, p. 10). In general he despised the classical bent of the
middle-class education most of his contemporaries, but not himself, had
suffered. Such an education provided a mass of irrelevant knowledge: "So
terribly in our education does the ornamental over-ride the useful!"
(1911, p. 14).
Spencer's answer to his question of what knowledge is of
most worth was, simply, Science. He meant it in the widest sense, but most of
his followers found that they could not follow him all the way. Even if they
did not accept his answer, they did accept the correctness of his question for
designers of a new and modern curriculum, and they accepted also his basic
principle&emdash;that the ultimate criterion for selecting content for the
curricula must be its utility in the assumed future life of the student.
The twentieth-century saw the proponents of Spencer's
conception of utility and his priorities of self-preservation, securing the
necessaries of life, good citizenship, and so on, grow increasingly important.
So Social Studies largely displaced History, classical learning of any kind has
largely disappeared in favor of more utilitarian studies, the arts in general
have given ground to practical preparation for everyday life, literature
receives less time than functional literacy activities and so on. Spencer's
success is measured in the degree to which schools and those who work in them
are no longer seen as central institutions in the cultural life of the society
at large. Indeed, it seems fair to say that those involved in the institutions
of schooling increasingly show a somewhat anti-intellectual bias.
The answer is not more of the old traditional curriculum.
That simply perpetuates the fruitless and dreary polemics of twentieth-century
educational discourse. Anyway, I am not here interested in answers, so much as
to identify or at least plausibly suggest how we have got it wrong from the
beginning. In the case of the curriculum what we got wrong was accepting that the
important question was "what knowledge is of most worth?" and the
catastrophe has followed accepting Spencer's belief that a fundamentally
utilitarian criterion would allow us to answer it.
And what is wrong with such a question, and a dominant
criterion of utility determining the curriculum? I read yesterday about the
poet Joseph Brodsky teaching a class at a leading American college and coming
to a reference to Ovid. He asked who was familiar with the reference. No one.
Who had heard of Ovid? No one. He stood stunned looking at this group of highly
intelligent young people, and could say only "You've been cheated."
Cheated out of an education by those who accepted Spencer's criterion. Well,
that's too easy, of course. The question is what should constitute an
education, and it is inadequate to assume an alternative and rebuke its
competitor because it doesn't share its conclusions. And, of course, it isn't
easy to make a compelling argument that a utilitarian criterion cannot produce
an adequate curriculum. "Adequate for what?" becomes the obvious
question. In the end we would have to come down to some Wittgensteinian forms
of life impasse.
But whatever conclusion or impasse we might reach from that
argument, Spencer's utilitarian influence on the curriculum was allied with his
principle that children's learning must always be effortless if it is to
conform properly "to the methods of nature" (1911, p. 52). Learning
must also be pleasurable because, "the rise of an appetite for any kind of
information implies that the unfolding mind has become fit to assimilate it,
and needs it for the purposes of growth" (1911, p. 51), and the
satisfaction of any natural appetite gives pleasure. Applying these criteria
means constantly revising curricula to exclude elements that are not learned
effortlessly and pleasurably. The result of applying these criteria has been
the catastrophic "dumbing-down" of the curriculum, particularly in
the early years of schooling.
The combined requirements of utility of content and
effortless and pleasurable learning results in often highly intelligent
students who are, in Lord Clark of Civilization's phrase, "ignorant as
swans."
Conclusion
So here we are with a general conception of education
powerfully influenced by the ideas Herbert Spencer. We have seen that the
beliefs on which he based his educational principles were wrong, and yet,
ironically, the educational principles have been accepted as almost beyond
question.
Beatrice Webb describes her early enchantment with Spencer's
ideas, the ferment of intellectual excitement that he created, and then her
disenchantment: "My case, I think, is typical of the rise and fall of
Herbert Spencer's influence over the men and women of my own generation"
(1926, p. 61). Spencer was the victim of one of the crueler but most telling
put-down in modern intellectual history. In talking with Thomas Huxley and
others, (and reported in 1909 by Karl Pearson) (Abrams, 1968, p. vii) the
inexorably philosophic Spencer said "You fellows would little think that I
wrote a tragedy when I was young." Huxley immediately said: "I know
what it was about." Spencer was surprised at this, and said it was
impossible that Huxley could know, as he had never mentioned it to anyone
before. But Huxley insisted, and Spencer challenged him to describe it. Huxley
replied: "It was the history of a beautiful induction killed by a nasty
little fact."
While Spencer's huge reputation and his magnificent
theoretical structures came crashing down under the discovery of nasty little
facts, the educational ideas derived from his flawed theoretical structures
soldiered on. It took time for them to gain a hold, particularly on American
education, but once they did they proved themselves immensely tenacious. As his
reputation in the wider intellectual world collapsed, Charles Eliot of Harvard
could note in 1910:
"The ideas on education which he put forward more than
fifty years ago have penetrated educational practice very
slowly&emdash;particularly in England; but they are now coming to prevail
in most civilized countries, and they will prevail more and more."
(Intro. to Spencer, 1911, p. viii)
It is not clear from the syntax of that sentence whether
England is to be classed among the civilized countries, but over the past
half-century Spencer's educational principles have gained ascendancy in his
home-land as well as in North America.
The beginning of public schooling was in the later
nineteenth-century, and we got wrong the conception of education that
determined teaching and the curriculum. Here we are with massive financial and
technical resources at hand to educate our children, but we are in a conceptual
mess, and the result is ignorance and waste of life in catastrophic proportion.
Bibliography
Abrams, Philip. (1968). The origins of British sociology:
1834-1914. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Cremin, Lawrence. (1961). The transformation of the school:
Progressivism in American education, 1876&endash;1957. New York: Knopf.
Egan, Kieran. (1997). The educated mind: How cognitive tools
shape our understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Fodor, Jerry. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Fodor, Jerry. (1985). "Précis of 'The modularity of
mind'." The behavioral and brain sciences, 8, 1-42.
Gould, Stephen Jay. (1977). Ontogeny and phylogeny.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hall, G. Stanley. (1904). Adolescence: Its psychology and
its relations to physiology, anthropology, sociology, sex, crime, religion, and
education (2 vols.). New York: D. Appleton.
Karmiloff-Smith, Annette. (1992). Beyond modularity: A
developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Rorty, Richard. (1989). Contingency, irony, and solidarity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Spencer, Herbert. (1851). Social statics. London: Chapman.
Spencer, Herbert. (1904). An autobiography. London: Williams
& Norgate. (First published 1888).
Spencer, Herbert. (1911). Essays on Education, Etc. (Charles
W. Eliot, intro.) London: Dent. (The constituent essays of this collection were
first published in the 1850s.)
Spencer, Herbert. (1966). "The development
hypothesis." In Essays: scientific, political, speculative. Vol. I. Osnabrück:
Otto Zeller. (Reprint of the 1891 edition of the Works of H. Spencer.)
Webb, Beatrice. (1971). My apprenticeship. Harmondsworth:
Penguin. (First published in 1926.)
|